Robert C. Jones, Ph.D.
February 2017
To possess inherent value and consequently, moral rights, requires that one has the capacity to be the subject of experiences that matter to oneself, what Regan famously termed being the subject of a life. This view, that the capacity for this kind of subjective experience confers upon its possessor inherent value, is both intuitive and meticulously argued for in the book.
[This tribute was originally posted at
Animal Liberation Currents.]
Like many animal liberationists, I came to an understanding of the plight of
our animal kin through Peter Singer’s Animal Liberation. Many people are
surprised to learn that this “father of the modern animal rights movement”
did not argue that nonhuman animals have rights, at least not in the moral,
philosophical sense. That case was to be made powerfully and convincingly
less than a decade later by Tom Regan. In The Case for Animal Rights,
Regan presented what was basically one long sustained and rigorous argument
for animal rights of the actual moral and philosophical kind.
Since its publication in 1983, in many ways, the book has stood in the
shadow of Animal Liberation. Yet for those less-than friendly to Singer’s
utilitarian framework, The Case for Animal Rights provided a sound
foundation upon which animal liberationists could make a case for
rights—inviolate rights—for nonhuman animals.
Though broadly Kantian, Regan’s approach rejected the notion (central to
Kant’s moral framework) that only “rational” beings (i.e., for all intents
and purposes, humans) possess moral value. By contrast, Regan argued that
what mattered morally is not rationality per se, but the capacity to be the
subject of experiences. However, not just any kind of subjective experience
warrants inherent value. To possess inherent value and consequently, moral
rights, requires that one has the capacity to be the subject of experiences
that matter to oneself, what Regan famously termed being the subject of a
life. This view, that the capacity for this kind of subjective experience
confers upon its possessor inherent value, is both intuitive and
meticulously argued for in the book. I cannot tell you how many times I have
referred to that passage on p. 243 of his book (I know the page number by
heart) where Regan outlines which physiological, emotional, psychological,
and cognitive capacities—over and above mere sentience—make one the
subject-of-a-life. So impressed was I by this aspect of Regan’s view that my
doctoral dissertation, focused on the moral significance of animal
cognition, came about in no small part due to my simply trying to flesh out
the moral ramifications of that passage. Of course, critics rightly pointed
out how even such a thoroughly worked out view had blind spots, lacunae that
Regan himself eventually came to fill then build upon.
Tom Regan was a pioneer in the struggle for the liberation of animals from
the bonds of institutional and systemic violence, oppression, and
domination. Though I never met the man, by all accounts he was what
Aristotle would have called a person of great virtue, a warm, kind,
compassionate human being. The world is a darker place now that he has left
us, but fortunately Tom Regan left behind a profound and indispensable body
of work to act as a beacon for animal liberationists to follow.
Read more at Tom Regan - Directory.
Return to Animal Rights Articles