It is truly astonishing and also rather tragic to find how timeless this 1989 speech is. Sadly, as we go through his ‘question and answer’ responses to the opponents of Animal Rights, we find the same tired old justifications are STILL being used.
Here, with what is still seen as one of the greatest animal rights speeches of all time, is Professor Tom Regan (1938 – 2017) who opened the debate “Does the Animal Kingdom Need a Bill of Rights” at the Royal Institute of Great Britain in 1989.
I have lost count of how many times I’ve listened to this over the
years. The talk is as spellbinding as it is quotable, but I couldn’t
find an accurate transcript. I therefore decided to transcribe it
myself, so the punctuation and emphases are mine.
It is truly astonishing and also rather tragic to find how timeless
it is. Sadly, as we go through his ‘question and answer’ responses
to the opponents of Animal Rights, we find the same tired old
justifications are STILL being used. The difference is that the
sheer number of our species’ victims is escalating year on year, so
as advocates we can’t afford to relax even slightly. Let us draw
inspiration from those like Professor Regan whose life’s work work
paved our way.
**************
The other animals humans eat, use in science, hunt, trap, and
exploit in a variety of other ways have a life of their own that is
of importance to them, apart from their utility to us. They are not
only in the world they are aware of it and also of what happens to
them, and what happens to them matters to them. Each has a life that
fares experientially better or worse for the one whose life it is.
Like us they bring a unified psychological presence to the world;
like us they are somebodys not somethings.
In these fundamental ways, the non-human animals in labs and on
farms for example, are the same as human beings, and so it is that
the ethics of our dealings with them – and with one another – must
rest on some of the same fundamental moral principles.
At its deepest level an enlightened human ethic is based on the
independent value of the individual. To treat human beings in ways
that do not honour their independent worth, to reduce them to the
status of tools or models or commodities for example, is to violate
that most basic of human rights; the right to be treated with
respect.
The philosophy of animal rights demands only the logic be respected,
for any argument that plausibly explains the independent value of
human beings, implies that other animals have the same value and
have it equally; and any argument that plausibly explains the right
of humans to be treated with respect, also implies that these other
animals have this same right, and have it equally.
Also, as a result of selective media coverage in the past – to which
this evening’s debate is a notable and praiseworthy exception – the
general public has tended to view advocates of animal rights in
exclusively negative terms. We are ‘anti-intellectual’,
‘anti-science’, ‘anti-rational’, ‘anti-human’. We stand ‘against’
justice and ‘for’ violence.
The truth, as it happens, is quite the reverse. The philosophy of
animal rights is on the side of reason, for it is not rational to
discriminate arbitrarily. And discrimination against nonhuman
animals is demonstrably arbitrary. It is wrong to treat weaker human
beings – especially those who are lacking in normal human
intelligence – as tools or models for example. It cannot be rational
therefore to treat other animals as if they were tools, models, and
the like, if their psychology is as rich as, or richer than, these
human beings.
The philosophy of animal rights is pro- not anti-science. This
philosophy is respectful of our best science in general, and all
evolutionary biology in particular. The latter teaches that, in
Darwin’s words, ‘Humans differ from many other animals in degree and
not in kind.’
Questions about line drawing to one side, it is obvious that the
animals used in laboratories, raised for food, and hunted for
pleasure, or trapped for profit, for example, are our psychological
kin. This is not fantasy. This is fact, supported by our best
science.
The philosophy of animal rights stands for not against justice.
We are not to violate the rights of the few so that the many might
benefit; slavery allows this, child labour allows this, all unjust
social institutions allow this. But not the philosophy of animal
rights whose highest principle is that of justice. The philosophy of
animal rights stands for peace and against violence. The fundamental
demand of this philosophy is to treat humans and other animals with
respect. This philosophy therefore, is a philosophy of peace. But it
is a philosophy that extends the demand for peace beyond the
boundaries of our species. For there is an undeclared war being
waged every day against countless millions of nonhuman animals. To
stand truly for peace, is to stand firmly against their ruthless
exploitation.
And what, aside from the common menu of media distortions, what will
be said by the opponents of animal rights?
Will the objection be that we are equating animals and humans in
every respect, when in fact humans and animals differ greatly?
But clearly, we are not saying that humans and other animals are the
same in every way; that dogs and cats can do calculus; or that pigs
and cows enjoy poetry.
What we are saying is that, like humans, many other animals have an
experiential welfare of their own. In this sense we and they are the
same. In this sense therefore, despite our many differences, we and
they are equal.
Will the objection be that we are saying that every human and every
animal has the same rights? That chicken should have the right to
vote and pigs the right to ballet lessons?
But of course, we are not saying this. All we are saying, is that
these animals and humans share one basic moral right; the right to
be treated with respect.
Will the objection be that because animals do not respect our
rights, we therefore have no obligation to respect their rights
either?
But there are many human beings who have rights and are unable to
respect the rights of others; young children and the mentally
enfeebled and deranged of all ages. In their case we do not say that
it is perfectly all right to treat them as tools or models or
commodities because they do not honour our rights. On the contrary
we recognise that we have a duty to treat them with respect. What is
true of cases involving these human beings is no less true of cases
involving other animals.
Will the objection be that if other animals do have more – even if
other animals do have moral rights – there are other more important
things that need our attention; world hunger and child abuse for
example, apartheid, drugs, violence to women, the plight of the
homeless. After – after – we take care of these problems then we can
worry about animal rights.
This objection misses the mark. For the rank-and-file of the animal
rights movement is composed of people, whose first line of service
is human service; doctors, nurses and other healthcare
professionals, people involved in a broad range of social services
from rape counselling to aiding victims of child abuse, or famine,
or discrimination; teachers at every level of education, ministers,
priests, rabbis. As the lives of these people demonstrate, the
choice thoughtful people face is not between either helping humans
or helping other animals.
One can do both. We should do both.
Will the objection be, finally, that no one has rights; not any
human being and not any other animal either; but rather that right
and wrong are a matter of acting to produce the best consequences,
being certain to count everyone’s interest and count equal interests
equally?
This moral philosophy, ‘utilitarianism’, has a long and venerable
history. Influential men and women past and present are among its
adherents, and yet it is a bankrupt moral philosophy if ever there
was one.
Are we seriously, seriously, to inquire into the interest of the
rapist before declaring rape wrong? Should we ask the child molester
whether his interest would be frustrated before condemning the
molestation of our children?
Remarkably a consistent utilitarianism demands that we ask these
questions, and in so demanding, relinquishes any claim on our
rational assent.
With regard to the philosophy of animal rights, then, is it
rational, impartial, scientifically informed? Does it stand for
peace and against injustice?
To these – to ALL these questions – the answer is an unqualified
‘yes’.
And as for the objections that are raised against this philosophy,
are those who accept it, able to offer rational, informed, answers?
Again, the answer is, ‘yes’.
In the battle of ideas, the philosophy of animal rights wins, its
critics lose.
It remains to be seen which side emerges as the victor in the
ongoing political battle between what is just and what is not.
Thank you.
Note from All-Creatures.org: Please also read and share from Tom Regan: Animal Rights 101: 10 Reasons For Animal Rights and Their Explanations